In part 1 we looked at Fesko’s chapter on Dooyeweerd in his Reforming
Apologetics: Retrieving the Classic Reformed Approach to Defending the Faith
and showed that it doesn’t give an accurate account of Dooyeweerd’s thought. My
hope is that reformed Thomists won’t dismiss Dooyeweerd on the basis of Fesko’s
presentation. There are no doubt important areas of disagreement between
Dooyeweerd and that of reformed Thomists, yet neither can benefit from
misreading and dismissing each other and I believe that it is possible to learn
from each other. In this post I will focus on two main claims that John Bolt
makes concerning Dooyeweerd in his chapter “Doubting Reformational
Anti-Thomism” in Aquinas Among the Protestants. While Bolt’s reflections
on his four “doubts” get closer to issues relevant for a discussion of
Dooyeweerd’s philosophy his evaluation is coloured by a serious misreading from
the beginning. This means that his doubts are not as incisive as they might
have been had he started with a more accurate and nuanced understanding. Concerning
the misinterpretations of Aquinas held by reformational thinkers Bolts writes “This
is a matter of academic integrity; followers of Jesus Christ are under an
obligation to be scrupulously fair to their opponents.” (p.131). I fully agree
with this principle. Reformational
thinkers and reformed Thomists need to do their best to understand each other
and hopefully this might even lead them to think of each other less as opponents.
The first claim that Bolt makes is that Dooyeweerd completely
rejects the thought of both Aquinas and Aristotle so that nothing of value can
be found in them. Bolt believes that Dooyeweerd even went as far as to hold
that Aquinas’ thought was apostate. This is tied to a second view that Bolt
attributes to Dooyeweerd which is that the scientific distinction between truth
and falsehood is a direct result of the religious distinction between
regenerate and unregenerate so that the two distinctions are collapsed. Based
on this reading Bolt continually comes up against obvious fact that Dooyeweerd
gives positive evaluation to many non-Christian thinkers and even incorporates
some of their views into his own philosophy. On this reading Dooyeweerd is both
unfairly critical of thinkers like Aquinas for incorporating ideas from non-Christian
philosophers while doing exactly the same just with different non-Christian philosophers.
The first claim can easily be dealt with. Here is what Bolt
writes: “According to Dooyeweerd the great medieval synthesis of Thomas and
others was an illicit joining of pagan religion with biblical faith. His
judgement is severe: “they were apostate in their direction” (Dooyeweerd 1979,
111)” (p.131). When we follow up the reference that Bolt gives we find that
Dooyeweerd is there discussing Greek religion and not medieval thought in
general or Thomas in particular. It is Greek religion that Dooyeweerd describes
as “apostate in their direction”. In contrast he writes that “For its part, the
Romanistic basic theme preserved at least to a degree its connection with the
divine Word-revelation” (RS I, 25). Dooyeweerd certainly has his criticisms of
Thomism, however he engaged in serious and friendly discussion with a number of
Thomist philosophers and never dismissed Aquinas out of hand. He wrote “There
is no doubt in my mind that Thomas sincerely intended to make Aristotle’s
metaphysics square with the church’s doctrine of creation. The only question is
whether this was possible within the framework of an accommodated Aristotelian
philosophy” (RS II, 366). Nowhere does Dooyeweerd describe Aquinas’ position as
a “joining of pagan religion with biblical faith”, this is simply an inaccurate
presentation of Dooyeweerd.
Dooyeweed
thought long and hard about the relationship between the Christian religion and
the philosophical enterprise. His account of this relationship is complex, was developed
over time and remains controversial even among his sympathetic readers. Even if
one ends up critical of what he has to say on this topic Dooyeweerd’s positive
philosophical framework is still worthy of consideration. To take one example,
David Koyzis and Jonathan Chaplin (a contributor to Aquinas Among the
Protestants) have argued that there are parallels and opportunity for
cooperation between Thomist and reformational philosophers in the area of
political philosophy.
A full
answer to Bolt’s second claim about Dooyeweerd would involve a discussion of
the complex issues just hinted at, however we can make considerable headway in
just considering Dooyeweerd’s approach to the philosophical tradition in
general. Bolt develops this second point in an indirect way through a criticism
of Kuyper that Bavink makes. It involves Kuyper’s claim that there are two
kinds of science, one that is based on a Christian starting point and a second,
diametrically opposed, that starts from a non-Christian starting point. Bavinck’s
argument is that this conflates “the scientific distinction between truth and
falsehood with the personal one between regenerate and unregenerate people” and
so commits “a logical fallacy”. Further “to identify the scientific work of the
regenerate with truth and that of the unregenerate with lies is categorically
false” (p.135). “It seems to me that Bavinck’s critique is also applicable to
Dooyeweerd” (p.135). Fully in line with this interpretation Bolts writes that Dooyeweerd
believed that “any observation about reality made by Aristotle would thereby,
for that very reason, be rendered suspect. I cannot see how this is a fair or
reasonable inference” (p.139). Bolt is absolutely right that such an inference
is neither fair nor reasonable, it is also a position that Dooyeweerd would
completely reject.
It is surprising
that Bolt insists on such an interpretation given that he makes reference to
Dooyeweerd’s article “Kuyper’s Philosophy of Science” where Dooyeweerd not only
makes a number of statements to the contrary but, like any philosopher, engages
in criticism and not mere dismissal, of positions he rejects. Near the start he
writes “Though bordering on redundancy, because it has been said so often
before: The Philosophy of the Cosmonomic Idea claims no infallibility, neither
for its positive philosophical conceptions nor with regard to its critique of
traditional philosophy” (p.132 of a draft translation). Dooyeweerd is clear
that he offers both his positive philosophical views and his philosophical
criticisms as ordinary examples of what fallible human philosophers do and so
open to the same evaluation as any other philosophy. Dooyeweerd repeatedly
argued against dogmatism in philosophy insisting that no philosophy should be
dismissed just because of its religious background. He wanted his Christian
philosophy to be taken seriously by non-Christian philosophers and equally
argued that “the Christian ground-motive refuses to allow any particular
philosophical movement to be excluded from the philosophical community
because of its point of departure.” (RS I, 29).
A typical
statement of Dooyeweerd’s found in the article cited by Bolt is “The Philosophy
of the Cosmonomic Idea has never defended the view that a philosophy springing
from a non-Christian root cannot contain important elements of truth” (p.134 of
draft version). So it is not clear why Bolt thinks that Dooyeweerd rejects
everything Aristotle says because it is a pagan author that says it. His actual
method and approach to the philosophical tradition is quite different. He
insists repeatedly that “it is an utter illusion to suppose that a philosophy
can develop itself in isolation” (quoted in Verburg’s Herman Dooyeweerd: The
life and work of a Christian philosopher p.346 compare similar statements
TWT 38, NC I. 115, 117, RS II, 26-27). This leads to an approach that seeks to
identify the moments of truth and insight in every philosophy. It is only in the
context of identifying insights in a philosophy that criticism of that
philosophy can become valid and worthwhile. Philosophical criticism involves
showing how a genuine insight goes awry, the task then is to incorporate the
insight within a philosophical framework that can give it more justice. This is
consistent with Dooyeweerd’s understanding of Christianity in relation to the
ground-motive of creation, fall and redemption. Every philosophical conception
should be considered within this framework. As Robert Sweetman has put it
recently: creation-fall-redemption is a spiritual impulse “in which one
approaches something open to encountering it with indications of its original
blessing, its marring and consequent ambiguity, and its reception of a new and
redemptive meaning by which its original blessing shines forth again and
becomes redolent of new possibilities.” (Tracing the lines 142-143) Dooyeweerd is happy to speak
of “data” or “structural states of affairs” that any philosophy is able to
recognise and must take account of within its framework. To show how this is
understood by Dooyeweerd I offer the following two quotes:
“In the
philosophical effort to account for [structural states of affairs] in the
context of a theoretical view of totality, there may be a noble competition
between all philosophical trends without discrimination. We do not claim a
privileged position for the Christian philosophy of the cosmonomic Idea in this
respect. For even the Christian ground-motive and the content of our
transcendental ground-Idea determined by it, do not give security against
fundamental mistakes in the accomplishment of our philosophical task” (NC I.
117)
“Every
philosophical current may contribute to the testing of its own and other
philosophical views with respect to data which, up to now, have been neglected.
For the discovery of this neglected state of affairs in our experiential
horizon is not the monopoly of a particular philosophical school. Thanks to
common grace, relative truths are to be found in every philosophy,
although the interpretation of such truths may appear to be unacceptable from
the biblical standpoint insofar as the philosophical interpretation turns out
to be ruled by a dialectical and apostate basic-motive. However, no philosophy
can prosper in isolation.” TWT 38
Once we have
taken this into account we will not be surprised to read Dooyeweerd talk about
an “important element of truth” in Aristotle’s substance concept (RS II, 264).
Nor that he recognises that “the distinction between potentiality and actuality
in reality has undoubtedly been a brilliant and fruitful discovery. It has
indeed enriched Western philosophical thinking … It is certainly not the
intention of the Philosophy of the Law-Idea to reject or minimize an
Aristotelian distinction that has proven fruitful.” (RS II, 290).
4 comments:
Thanks for this useful and insightful analysis Rudi. Blessings, Steve
Rudi, I hope you can expand this to a review of related books
Romel and Steve, thanks for your positive comments.
I suspect that my good friend John Bolt is reading Dooyeweerd while hearing the voices of rabid Dooyeweerdians who quote the "master" without themselves having wrestled with the problems Dooyeweerd dealt with.
but his defamatory claims are inexcusable.
harry VAn Dyke
Post a Comment